
In his earlier career, Kant was a
rationalist. He believed the mind was capable of possessing empirical knowledge
of the world apart from sense experience. But then Kant was introduced to the
work of David Hume. As Kant puts it, “I was awakened from my dogmatic slumber.”
As a result, Kant was set on the path toward what would become known as his “Copernican
Revolution” in epistemology. Just as Copernicus had thought, like everyone else,
that the sun moved around the earth until he realized it was the other way
around, Kant believed that philosophy had it just as backwards when it came to
the mind-object relationship. Rather than objects impressing themselves on the
human mind, it seemed to Kant that the mind was actually the agent impressing
and imposing itself on the objects of sense experience. Kant believed that
knowledge is a due to the inherent nature and structure of the mind. The mind
of man is not the passive wax like that in an old-fashioned phonograph, being
written upon by sense data. Instead, the mind is active in organizing the sense
data into categories of the understanding. Essentially then, Kant believed that
the human mind is active in constructing human knowledge. Contrary to
empiricism, the mind is not a blank sheet of paper filling up with sense data
through our experience.
Kant then believed that the mind
does not revolved around sense experience. Instead he suggested that knowledge
is the conformance of objects to the mind. This would seem then to explain how
we could know laws of nature. If they are located in the mind, and we can know
the mind, then it follows that we can know such laws. Kant divides reality into
two realms: the noumenal and the phenomenal. Noumenal things are things that
trigger our sense experience but they are unknowable in themselves. The
phenomenal world is the world as we experience it through the structure and
organizing activity of our minds. They are intelligible, rational, structured,
and knowable. We see how Kant solves the problem of possessing knowledge of
synthetic a priori truth. But how
does this solve for the reconciliation between scientific knowledge and our
religious view of the world. Kant says that we cannot know things like the
immaterial soul or God or eternality. Instead, we believe them on faith.
Kant’s program we call Transcendental Idealism. It is called ‘transcendental’
because it is not occupied with objects, but rather with how we can possibly
know things about objects even before we experience them. The knowledge
transcends experience. It is called idealism because quite frankly, we cannot
know objects as they are in themselves. We only know the appearances of objects
as they are experienced by the senses. And these objects are merely
representations of things, they are not the things in themselves. The human
mind denies access to the things in themselves in that it actively structures
the sense experience into categories we know a priori.
The implications of Kant's Transcendental Idealism on Christian theology are significant. For starters, knowledge of God is destroyed along with knowledge of self and of anything that is not part of the physical universe. To say we take it on faith is viewed as somehow not enough to qualify as knowledge. But that is not the sort of faith we mean when we talk about Christian faith. Modern Christians are about to be confronted more and more with this sort philosophical speculation as the shift in thought moves away from the Bible as God's Word and more brazenly toward man as the measure of all things. This has been the case for some time now but lets just say the pretense of American Christianity is evaporating before our eyes and it is only prudent for us to prepare ourselves to enter these conversations. Over the next several weeks I will provide fodder for evangelizing the many types of skeptics Christians encounter or will begin to encounter in their near future.
No comments:
Post a Comment